The Collatz Conjecture, also known as the Conjecture, is one of the
unsolved problems in number theory. The setting of the problem is simple. Let’s
define
as
(1) |
The conjecture states that for any n, if you apply this function enough times, it will hit 1. In this paper, I will be calling this function the step function.
The previous definition of the step function is good. However, it is expressed partially mathematically. A person might use this function to fix such an issue.
(2) |
This function is equal to 1 when x is odd and equal to 0 when the number is even. We can use such a function to define the step function.
(3) |
This is a better formula. However, this isn’t defined for real numbers x because of
. We will devise a different formula to make one that works with real
numbers. The formula should oscillate back and forth between two lines, the
and the
. We know that a function that oscillates between
and
is defined as
(4) |
Where is any function oscillating between -1 and 1. Now, again, let’s redefine
the step function.
Let’s pick a to be so that the frequency of the cos wave would be 1.
Then
The final function looks like this.
(5) (6) (7) |
Such a function is defined for all real numbers, not only for integers. A graph of such a function looks like the following.
The two lines here are blue and violet. They are the and the
. The red curve is the step function using the formula (5). This formula will
be used for the step function throughout the paper. What about defining the
function using
?
As with let us set the a to
. Then let us calculate b.
Then the final equation using looks like the following.
(8) |
Another way to write the step function is the following.
(9) |
First let’s define some basic lemmmas.
Lemma 1
This follows right from the initial definition of the Collatz Conjecture.
Lemma 2
This is also quite obvivous, such lemma comes from the function’s graph. An
example of a number that saticfies the statement is . Consider the section
of the step function graph from 0 to 0.2.
Looking at this graph, notice the section where . Let’s define H as
the following.
Def 1
Then we can state the following.
Lemma 3
We can even state something stronger than this.
Theorem 1
When dealing with paths developed by iteratively applying the step function,
a simple idea comes to mind when considering the similarities: Call two
numbers alike if the path until 1 of one number is contained within the
second number’s path as a prefix. A related definition I will introduce is
similarity; two numbers are considered similar if one number’s path is until a
number less than itself is contained within the same kind of path of the second
number as a prefix. I will denote the set of all similar numbers to as
, and the set of all alike numbers to
as
. Let us look at
how to compute similar numbers; as an example, pick
then one
must first calculate the path til a number less than 5 (denoted as
)
(10) |
Let us now write down this path as a function by applying the exact same
operations done to the numbers , but now with
.
(11) |
Then, the claim of the fundamental theorem is as follows:
(12) |
(13) |
(14) |
In other words, any for which
is similar to
. The
only way for this statement to be untrue is that we have broken the rules
somewhere.
Case 1) We somewhere divide by two an odd number.
Case 2) We 3x + 1 a even number.
In the first case, whatever comes next will never hit a hole number, so it won’t be registered as similar. In the second case, an even number when dividing by two, we will return to case 1. This empowers one to calculate similar numbers and their properties efficiently.
For any the set
has the following form.
(15) |
Thus, similar numbers are distributed in a very particular way throughout the
natural numbers; the difference between any two consecutive similar numbers is a
power of two. This allows us to introduce a concept such as the coefficient of
similarity of two natural numbers (denoted as , which is defined to be
the logarithm base 2 of the constant difference between two consecutive similar
numbers. Using the previous example, one can conclude that
,
because
.
We can also make theorems about the . For example, it is
trivial to realize that if
(meaning
and
are not similar),
then.
(16) |
Consider and
then there must be no
and
that the following is
true.
(17) |
Meaning
(18) |
For example, let us take numbers 3 and 5. Because we know that
.
Consider Collatz Conjecture false, then a number must exist such that the path
is infinite. This is a bit hard to work with; we can replace this with an analogous
statement that
has an infinite path until a number less than itself; in other
words,
never goes lower. This can be easily achieved by introducing induction
over the natural numbers or simply selecting the smallest counterexample.
Here, I will try to consider some examples of infinite paths and prove their
non-existence to understand better the nature of the paths of the counterexample
numbers.
Let us consider an infinite path, where the operations applied to the
number would interchange one after another. The goal here is to consider
the value of as we add more and more operations; in a sense,
I will analyze the behavior of
in the limit of interactions of
the step-function. I will denote by
the generated path after
iterations.
SIM#(I2(x)) = {x ∈ ℕ∣3x + 1 ≡ 0 (mod 2)} | ||
SIM#(I4(x)) = | ||
SIM#(I6(x)) = ... = {x ∈ ℕ∣27x + 19 ≡ 0 (mod 8)} | ||
SIM#(I8(x)) = ... = {x ∈ ℕ∣81x + 65 ≡ 0 (mod 16)} |
It is quite simple to prove and observe the general formula for such an equation.
(19) |
Due to , one can simplify the equation even further.
(20) |
And then again, noticing the factor of , we can substitute in
,
thus the needed modular equality needed to be solved is the following.
(21) |
Such equality can be easily solved; one must find multiples of , such that they
are divisible by
; in other words,
(22) |
One can see that due to the fundamental theorem of arithmetic, , thus
, where
is any natural number. Going backward from here,
back to the original equation, we are left with an exact equation describing
.
(23) |
Let be the minimal value of the set
, then as
, we
have
, thus there exists no natural number, such that it has such infinite
path.